Georg Cantor

скачати

Georg Cantor Essay, Research Paper

Georg Cantor

I. Georg Cantor

Georg Cantor founded set theory and introduced the concept of infinite numbers

with his discovery of cardinal numbers. He also advanced the study of

trigonometric series and was the first to prove the nondenumerability of the

real numbers. Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor was born in St. Petersburg,

Russia, on March 3, 1845. His family stayed in Russia for eleven years until the

father’s sickly health forced them to move to the more acceptable environment of

Frankfurt, Germany, the place where Georg would spend the rest of his life.

Georg excelled in mathematics. His father saw this gift and tried to push his

son into the more profitable but less challenging field of engineering. Georg

was not at all happy about this idea but he lacked the courage to stand up to

his father and relented. However, after several years of training, he became so

fed up with the idea that he mustered up the courage to beg his father to become

a mathematician. Finally, just before entering college, his father let Georg

study mathematics. In 1862, Georg Cantor entered the University of Zurich only

to transfer the next year to the University of Berlin after his father’s death.

At Berlin he studied mathematics, philosophy and physics. There he studied under

some of the greatest mathematicians of the day including Kronecker and

Weierstrass. After receiving his doctorate in 1867 from Berlin, he was unable to

find good employment and was forced to accept a position as an unpaid lecturer

and later as an assistant professor at the University of Halle in1869. In 1874,

he married and had six children. It was in that same year of 1874 that Cantor

published his first paper on the theory of sets. While studying a problem in

analysis, he had dug deeply into its foundations, especially sets and infinite

sets. What he found baffled him. In a series of papers from 1874 to 1897, he was

able to prove that the set of integers had an equal number of members as the set

of even numbers, squares, cubes, and roots to equations; that the number of

points in a line segment is equal to the number of points in an infinite line, a

plane and all mathematical space; and that the number of transcendental numbers,

values such as pi(3.14159) and e(2.71828) that can never be the solution to any

algebraic equation, were much larger than the number of integers. Before in

mathematics, infinity had been a sacred subject. Previously, Gauss had stated

that infinity should only be used as a way of speaking and not as a mathematical

value. Most mathematicians followed his advice and stayed away. However, Cantor

would not leave it alone. He considered infinite sets not as merely going on

forever but as completed entities, that is having an actual though infinite

number of members. He called these actual infinite numbers transfinite numbers.

By considering the infinite sets with a transfinite number of members, Cantor

was able to come up his amazing discoveries. For his work, he was promoted to

full professorship in 1879. However, his new ideas also gained him numerous

enemies. Many mathematicians just would not accept his groundbreaking ideas that

shattered their safe world of mathematics. One of these critics was Leopold

Kronecker. Kronecker was a firm believer that the only numbers were integers and

that negatives, fractions, imaginaries and especially irrational numbers had no

business in mathematics. He simply could not handle actual infinity. Using his

prestige as a professor at the University of Berlin, he did all he could to

suppress Cantor’s ideas and ruin his life. Among other things, he delayed or

suppressed completely Cantor’s and his followers’ publications, belittled his

ideas in front of his students and blocked Cantor’s life ambition of gaining a

position at the prestigious University of Berlin. Not all mathematicians were

hostile to Cantor’s ideas. Some greats such as Karl Weierstrass, and long-time

friend Richard Dedekind supported his ideas and attacked Kronecker’s actions.

However, it was not enough. Cantor simply could not handle it. Stuck in a third-

rate institution, stripped of well-deserved recognition for his work and under

constant attack by Kronecker, he suffered the first of many nervous breakdowns

in 1884. In 1885 Cantor continued to extend his theory of cardinal numbers and

of order types. He extended his theory of order types so that now his previously

defined ordinal numbers became a special case. In 1895 and 1897 Cantor published

his final double treatise on sets theory. Cantor proves that if A and B are sets

with A equivalent to a subset of B and B equivalent to a subset of A then A and

B are equivalent. This theorem was also proved by Felix Bernstein and by Schr?

der. The rest of his life was spent in and out of mental institutions and his

work nearly ceased completely. Much too late for him to really enjoy it, his

theory finally began to gain recognition by the turn of the century. In 1904, he

was awarded a medal by the Royal Society of London and was made a member of both

the London Mathematical Society and the Society of Sciences in Gottingen. He

died in a mental institution on January 6, 1918. Today, Cantor’s work is widely

used in the many fields of mathematics. His theory on infinite sets reset the

foundation of nearly every mathematical field and brought mathematics to its

modern form.

II. Infinity

Most everyone is familiar with the infinity symbol . How many is

infinitely many? How far away is “from here to infinity”? How big is infinity?

We can’t count to infinity. Yet we are comfortable with the idea that there are

infinitely many numbers to count with: no matter how big a number you might come

up with, someone else can come up with a bigger one: that number plus one–or

plus two, or times two. There simply is no biggest number. Is infinity a number?

Is there anything bigger than infinity? How about infinity plus one? What’s

infinity plus infinity? What about infinity times infinity? Children to whom the

concept of infinity is brand new, pose questions like this and don’t usually get

very satisfactory answers. For adults, these questions don’t seem to have very

much bearing on daily life, so their unsatisfactory answers don’t seem to be a

matter of concern. At the turn of the century Cantor applied the tools of

mathematical rigor and logical deduction to questions about infinity in search

of satisfactory answers. His conclusions are paradoxical to our everyday

experience, yet they are mathematically sound. The world of our everyday

experience is finite. We can’t exactly say where the boundary line is, but

beyond the finite, in the realm of the transfinite, things are different.

Sets and Set Theory

Cantor is the founder of the branch of mathematics called Set Theory, which is

at the foundation of much of 20th century mathematics. At the heart of Set

Theory is a hall of mirrors–the paradoxical infinity. Georg Cantor was known to

have said, “I see it, but I do not believe it,” about one of his proofs. The set

is the mathematical object which Cantor scrutinized. He defined a set as any

collection of well-distinguished and well-defined objects considered as a single

whole. A collection of matching dishes is a set, as well as a collection of

numbers. Even a collection of seemingly unrelated things like, {television,

aardvark, car, 6} is a set. They are well-defined and can be distinguished from

one another. Sets can be large or small. They can also be finite and infinite. A

finite set has a finite number of members. No matter how many there are, given

enough time, you can count them all. Cantor’s surprising results came when he

considered sets that had an infinite number of members. Sets such as all of the

counting numbers, or all of the even numbers are infinite sets. In order to

study infinite sets, Cantor first formalized many of the things that are

intuitive and obvious about finite sets. At first, it seems like these

formalizations are just a whole lot of trouble, a way of making simple things

complicated. Because the formalisms are clearly correct, however, they provide a

powerful tool for examining things that are not so simple, intuitive or obvious.

Cantor needed a way to compare the sizes of sets, some method for determining

whether sets had the same number of members. If two sets didn’t have the same

number of members, he needed a method for telling which one was larger. Of

course this is simple for finite sets. You count the members in both sets. If

the number is the same, they are the same size. If the number of members in one

set is greater than the number of members in the other, then that set is larger.

You can’t count the members in an infinite set, though, so this method won’t

work for comparing their sizes. If there are two infinite sets, one must need

some other way to tell if one is larger. The formal notion that Cantor used for

comparing sizes of sets is the idea of a one-to-one correspondence. A one-to-one

correspondence pairs up the members of one set with the members of another. Sets

which can be matched to each other in this sense are said to have the same

cardinality. We could pair up the elements of the imaginary set {television,

aardvark, car, 6} with the numbers {1,2,3,4}. It is possible to do this so that

one member of each set is paired up with one member of the other, no member is

left out, and no member has more than one partner. Then we can be sure that the

set{1,2,3,4} has the same number of members as the set {television, aardvark,

car, 6}. one-to-one correspondence:

{television, aardvark, car, 6}

{ 1,2,3, 4}

So, what is bigger? infinity+X? infinity+infinity ? Or infinity(infinity)? To

calculate which is bigger cantor used sets and one-to-one correspondence.

These one-to-one correspondence sets show that even though we add an unknown

variable, multiply by two, and square a set, the upper and lower sets still

remain equal. Since we will never run out of numbers any correspondence set with

two infinite values will be equal. All these sets clearly have the same

cardinality since its members can be put in a one-to-one correspondence with

each other on and on forever. These sets are said to be countably infinite and

their cardinality is denoted by the Hebrew letter aleph with a subscript nought,

.

OTHER INFINITIES

Cantor thought once you start dealing with infinities, everything is the same

size. This did not turn out to be the case. Cantor developed an entire theory of

transfinite arithmetic, the arithmetic of numbers beyond infinity. Although the

sizes of the infinite sets of counting numbers, even numbers, odd numbers,

square numbers, etc., are the same, there are other sets, the set of numbers

that can be expressed as decimals, for instance, that are larger. Cantor’s work

revealed that there are hierarchies of ever-larger infinities. The largest one

is called the Continuum. Some mathematicians who lived at the end of the 19th

century did not want to accept his work at all. The fact that his results were

so paradoxical was not the problem so much as the fact that he considered

infinite sets at all. At that time, some mathematicians held that mathematics

could only consider objects that could be constructed directly from the counting

numbers. You can’t list all the elements in an infinite set, they said, so

anything that you say about infinite sets is not mathematics. The most powerful

of these mathematicians was Leopold Kronecker who even developed a theory of

numbers that did not include any negative numbers. Although Kronecker did not

persuade very many of his contemporaries to abandon all conclusions that relied

on the existence of negative numbers, Cantor’s work was so revolutionary that

Kronecker’s argument that it “went too far” seemed plausible. Kronecker was a

member of the editorial boards of the important mathematical journals of his day,

and he used his influence to prevent much of Cantor’s work from being published

in his lifetime. Cantor did not know at the time of his death, that not only

would his ideas prevail, but that they would shape the course of 20th century

mathematics.

Додати в блог або на сайт

Цей текст може містити помилки.

A Free essays | Essay
18.2кб. | download | скачати


Related works:
Georg Handel
Architecture Georg Muche
Der Hessische Landbote By Georg Buechner(in German)
© Усі права захищені
написати до нас